Divine Attributes

Knowing the Covenantal God of Scripture

This title was previously available on NetGalley and is now archived.
Buy on Amazon Buy on Waterstones.com
*This page contains affiliate links, so we may earn a small commission when you make a purchase through links on our site at no additional cost to you.
Send NetGalley books directly to your Kindle or Kindle app

1
To read on a Kindle or Kindle app, please add kindle@netgalley.com as an approved email address to receive files in your Amazon account. Click here for step-by-step instructions.
2
Also find your Kindle email address within your Amazon account, and enter it here.
Pub Date 4 May 2021 | Archive Date 4 Jul 2021

Talking about this book? Use #DivineAttributes #NetGalley. More hashtag tips!


Description

This book offers a clear and constructive account of the nature and attributes of God. It addresses the doctrine of God from exegetical, historical, and constructive-theological perspectives, bringing the biblical portrayal of God in relationship to the world into dialogue with prominent philosophical and theological questions. The book engages questions such as: Does God change? Does God have emotions? Does God know the future? Is God entirely good and loving? How can God be one and three? Chapters correspond to the major metaphysical and moral attributes of God.

This book offers a clear and constructive account of the nature and attributes of God. It addresses the doctrine of God from exegetical, historical, and constructive-theological perspectives...


Advance Praise

“Divine attribution is often overlooked in its importance for Christian reflection, but it is critical to reckon with the identity and character of the One Christians worship. Peckham’s latest book provides an accessible framework for this topic, all the while demonstrating a resounding attentiveness to the biblical witness as contemporary discussions are judiciously elaborated.”—Daniel Castelo, professor of dogmatic and constructive theology, Seattle Pacific University and Seminary


“In this rich and careful depiction of the canonical God, Peckham paints for us the holistic portrait of God beholden to neither strict classical theism nor open theism. By tracing the native Hebraic logic of covenantal theism throughout the Old and New Testaments, many conflicts and paradoxes fade into the coherent structure of the canon’s thinking. For theologians, biblical scholars, and students, this prudent volume will reward all who feast upon it. This is compulsory reading for any theologian who seeks to make necessary connections with the biblical texts.”—Dru Johnson, associate professor of biblical and theological studies and director of the Center for Hebraic Thought, The King’s College, New York City; host of the OnScript podcast

“Following his ‘covenantal,’ scripturally anchored method of working constructive theology, John Peckham brings to us a highly sophisticated and fine-tuned account of the divine attributes. While properly engaging ancient discussions about the ‘God of the Philosophers’ and the current systematic and philosophical theological critiques of the ‘God of Classical Theism,’ Peckham allows Scripture to be the source, norm, and final arbiter. Thereby, this fine study avoids the trap of attempting a description of the living God of the Bible in abstract, half-empty formal terms; instead, a dynamic, inviting, and spiritually nourishing testimony to who God is and what God does emerges out of a careful exegetical-systematic reflection.”—Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, professor of systematic theology, Fuller Theological Seminary; docent of ecumenics, University of Helsinki

“This volume on the divine attributes and ‘covenantal theism’ is a superb work of theology. It is thorough, nuanced, and balanced. As in his other works, Peckham is both winsome and bold: he winsomely engages important age-old and more recent theological conversations and controversies, and he boldly challenges certain theological positions while confidently articulating and defending the considerable merits of covenantal theism.”—Paul Copan, Pledger Family Chair of Philosophy and Ethics, Palm Beach Atlantic University; author of Loving Wisdom: A Guide to Philosophy and Christian Faith

“In this accessible and engaging work, John Peckham outlines and engages with many of the ongoing debates in philosophical theology about God’s attributes, exploring the biblical warrant for many of classical theism’s claims about what God must be like if he is indeed maximally great. What emerges from Peckham’s own biblically rooted approach is an immensely attractive picture of a God who is ‘great’ in terms of his capacity for, and commitment to, relationships of love. This book covers a tremendous amount of ground in a short space and is very useful as a resource for ongoing discussions of perfect being theology. The book also serves as a penetrating challenge to rethink the question of whether our starting point for a doctrine of God should be philosophical ideas of perfection or biblical themes of covenant. Thoughtful, informative, and highly recommended.”—Kevin Kinghorn, professor of philosophy and religion, Asbury Seminary

“This book provides an excellent exposition and defense of moderate classical theism. Peckham displays vast knowledge of a wide range of biblical, philosophical, historical, and contemporary sources. He offers sagacious evaluation of controversial issues, and his covenantal approach is a significant contribution. After reading this book one feels a deep sense of gratitude for gaining a better understanding of the God whom we worship.”—Andrew T. Loke, associate professor, Hong Kong Baptist University

“John Peckham’s Divine Attributes offers a much-needed voice in contemporary debates over the nature of God. For quite some time, the debates seem to be between those who wish to maintain a strict classical conception of God and those who affirm an open and relational model of God. What Peckham offers is a genuine middle ground between these two views that affirms traditional understandings of divine foreknowledge but also offers a relational and covenantal God with the rich emotional life that Scripture proclaims. Divine Attributes will be a game changer for debates about the nature of God. Strict classical theists and open theists must deal with the powerful biblical case that Peckham presents. If you are looking for a theology text that is faithful to the biblical witness and sensitive to the philosophical challenges that arise from thinking about the nature of God, then Divine Attributes is the book for you.”—R. T. Mullins, Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies

“Divine attribution is often overlooked in its importance for Christian reflection, but it is critical to reckon with the identity and character of the One Christians worship. Peckham’s latest book...

Available Editions

EDITION Other Format
ISBN 9781540961259
PRICE US$32.00 (USD)
PAGES 336

Available on NetGalley

NetGalley Shelf App (EPUB)
Send to Kindle (EPUB)

Average rating from 2 members


Featured Reviews

John C. Peckham’s “Divine Attributes” is an incredible theological tapestry that will inform, challenge, and invigorate one’s faith. John’s attention to detail and overarching narrative is done with beautiful wisdom and finesse. I highly recommend this book to all theologically and biblically minded Christians!

Was this review helpful?

Within Evangelicalism, the doctrine of God has become a battlefield on which is fought a war of theological method. Rhyne Putman and Craig Carter are representative of the extreme sides of inductive (or abductive) and deductive theological methods. Somewhere in the middle, but leaning towards the inductive side of things, is John C. Peckham. I was pleased to receive a copy of Peckham’s new book, Divine Attributes from the publisher (Baker Academic). I found Peckham’s methodology refreshing in light of the recent Evangelical Neo-Thomists I have been reading (see my reviews of None Greater, Contemplating God with the Great Tradition, and All That Is in God), and his treatment of the debate over the “God of the Philosophers” is strong. There is much good in this book; I would have given it 4/5 stars if not for the later chapters on libertarian free will. The extensive interaction with commentators and Scripture is highly commendable.

<b>Summary</b>

In Divine Attributes, Peckham outlines what he calls “covenantal theism.” He sets out to address “some core question about the nature and attributes of God, focusing on what we have biblical warrant to affirm with respect to such questions, in order to better understand the living God whom Christians worship and to whom Christian pray” (loc. 138). He offers “a constructive account of divine attributes, brining biblical portrayals of God into dialogue with core questions in the contemporary discussion of classical theism” (loc 533). His approach to theology is what he calls “canonical,” which approaches the Bible as a single book and identifies theology as what we are warranted to believe from the teaching of the Bible. Accordingly, Peckham writes, “the definitive question this book seeks to address is, What do we have biblical warrant to (confidently) claim relative to the doctrine of God?” (loc 809).
In Chapter 1, Peckham orients his book to the present debate over the “God of the Philosophers,” orienting his book in contrast to “strict classical theists” on the one hand (e.g. James Dolezal and Paul Helm) and open theists or process theists on the other. He rightly observes that strict classical theists too readily charge their opponents with the “Hellenistic thesis,” which is the claim that critics of Classical theism are guilty of presenting a false antithesis between biblical and Greek thought. I agree with Peckham that this charge is thrown out too quickly, without attention to the nuance behind the various critiques of “strict classical theism.” In Chapter 2, Peckham argues that God is voluntarily passible—experiences emotions—but that these are not a limitation to his perfection, nor do they compromise his aseity. He also argues that God is immutable in his essence but that he experiences change in various other senses. Chapter 3 defends a view of timed eternity, where God experiences a temporality analogous to ours but without beginning or end. God is also omnipresent minimally with reference to his exhaustive knowledge and ability to act in all places but also in his ability to be particularly present in particular places as he chooses. In Chapter 4, Peckham argues that God has exhaustive knowledge, including foreknowledge. However, this foreknowledge is compatible with libertarian free will. The following chapter (Chapter 5) argues for a view of “sovereign providence” where God creates and sustains all things but permits his creatures significant, libertarian freedom. Peckham defines libertarian freedom as the ability to will other than God desires (loc 4142). God does not act determinately on the human or angelic will, so free human causality is a significant factor in the presence of evil in the world. Building on this position, Peckham deals with theodicy in Chapter 6, providing several perspectives on the Problem of Evil. He endorses Plantinga’s free will defence and argues that much evil is a result of God’s covenanting with humans, angels, and creation. That is, God has committed himself to give humans free will, he has committed to giving angels a certain level of jurisdiction in this world to wage cosmic warfare against himself, and he established laws by which the creation functions which he has committed to not supervene. Chapter 7 considers the Trinity, rejecting Eternal Functional Subordination and accepting the social trinitarian doctrine of three genuine persons who share a perichoretic unity. Chapter 8 brings the argument to a close with an overview of the ground covered. For those interested, Peckham commits himself to the following positions relative to contemporary debates: accepts libertarian freedom and election by foreknowledge (Arminianism); rejects Eternal Functional Subordination; rejects eternal generation and procession, along with Christ’s eternal sonship; rejects bipartite exegesis; accepts Social Trinitarianism; rejects strong immutability, strict aseity, strict simplicity, and strong impassibility; and accepts foreknowledge and omniscience.

<b>Evaluation</b>

Peckham writes clearly and there is much I appreciated and with which I agreed in the book, particularly in the first 4 chapters. I found his approach to theological method laudable in light of many of the approaches I have read recently (though I would not go so far as giving it wholesale endorsement). However, there were several areas of considerable weakness in the book. In general, the argument misses the mark in two significant areas, the depth could be improved in some areas, and he leaves several significant loose ends.

<i>Areas where the argument falls flat</i>
First, throughout the book, he indicates that “Classical Christian Theism” was not a uniform position throughout the history of the church and that there was significant diversity among the Patristic and Medieval Fathers. Though I would not deny diversity, Peckham is wrong in his appeals to the diversity of scholarly opinion. He relies primarily on Gavrilyuk’s monograph The Suffering of the Impassible God and several contemporary theologians; he does not offer a significant representation of the patristic scholarship. My PhD concerns 4th and 5th-century theology in the areas where Peckham suggests there is great diversity: to the contrary, the fathers and the contemporary mainstream philosophical tradition are largely on the same page with issues of impassibility, immutability, incomprehensibility, and simplicity. The Fathers assumed a basic doctrine of God that is evident in their writings but not frequently argued. The evidence is far more uniform than Peckham claims. I do not believe Tradition is normative for us, but it would be disingenuous to ignore the significant ways that Peckham’s theology departs from the mainstream Christian tradition.
Second, his argument for libertarianism fails to meet the most significant challenges facing the doctrine. I have argued for the inadequacy of libertarian freedom and Arminian soteriology in my book Prevenient Grace (Teleioteti 2020), but I will summarize a few issues here. In terms of his argument, Peckham dismisses the significant philosophical challenges to libertarianism in Chapter 4. He suggests that because the Bible teaches both libertarianism and foreknowledge they must be compatible. However, in chapter 5, he then argues that the biblical data may support either determinism or libertarianism. Clearly, the Bible does not teach libertarianism in the unambiguous way that Chapter 4 requires. If he were to permit the significant philosophical challenges facing libertarianism to be entertained, the evidence for determinism is significantly increased. More importantly, his treatment of determinism does not present the strongest possible opponent. He suggests that Calvinistic determinism means that God is the primary cause of all things (such that all things are caused immediately by God’s will). This is not correct: though “soft-determinism” does believe that all things have a cause and that all causes are fundamentally rooted in God’s decree, this leaves significant space for secondary causality, such as a human decision making and will. Indeed, his definition of libertarian is compatible with “soft-determinism,” such that creatures are able to will other than that which God desires. However, he also implies the converse position that God cannot act determinately in relation to the human will; this is a position that is biblically indefensible. Peckham does not deal with the most significant problems with this position, namely, the biblical teaching about total depravity and its solution, regeneration (see my Prevenient Grace). Many of his arguments against determinism have been adequately answered in my book or in others, and many of these problems are equally problematic for libertarians (such as the claim that God cannot will contradictory things).

<i>Areas where greater depth could be desired</i>
There are other areas where the argument could be deepened. Treatment of omnipresence in Divine Attributes does not sufficiently address what exactly is meant by “presence.” The digital age has illumined our understanding of presence greatly—at least I think it has. For example, in a very real sense, I can be present in Germany through a Skype conversation. However, we would recognize this as diminished presence, it is “not the same” as in-person presence. But imagine if I was able to hug, shake a hand, be present three-dimensionally, and act in every way that I could in Australia. Such mediated presence would be undeniably true presence. However, a human present in such a way would lose their presence elsewhere because they cannot maintain the focus and attention to function in both places simultaneously. However, if God is not limited in this way, then he can be fully present wherever he wishes, and make himself more evidently present in particular places. That is, God is presented as giving his attention and being physically present in “heaven,” where he is attended to be a multitude of angels. Simultaneously, he is especially present with His people in the Temple and able to give them His unique attention. In the New Testament age, He is present in this way with all of His people. He is present in oversight of the nations, and occasionally physically present in unique theophanies. Because God is not restricted by the human cognitive restrictions on attention, He can give His focused attention on several places simultaneously and act with equal power and efficiency in all places simultaneously. God can by spatially present in some places while giving his attention simultaneously elsewhere where he has no spatial presence. Unlike humans, physical presence does not preclude God’s true presence elsewhere.
In the second last chapter, Peckham’s short treatment of the Trinity leaves much to be desired. On the one hand, his rejection of Christ’s eternal sonship and the Father’s eternal fatherhood is far more significant than Peckham suggests. I have not read of such a move in the history of the Church nor among modern Evangelicals; it is a radical departure from the Christian tradition to suggest that Christ’s sonship was a result of the incarnation. I hardly think it is justified by Luke 1:35! Furthermore, I am not convinced that a unity of perichoresis is sufficient to account for the biblical portrayal of God as one (e.g. Deut 6:4-5). This is the perennial issue with social trinitarianism: proponents cannot sufficiently account for the biblical presentation of God’s unity.

<i>Some loose ends</i>
Finally, Peckham leaves a significant loose end in his treatment of the Incarnation and his claims about God’s essence. Peckham rejects significant elements of the classical Christian metaphysic, yet he maintains throughout that God has an “essence.” I am not sure that such a claim is ontologically coherent when its other attendant features are stripped away. It is important to maintain that there is a significant way in which God does not change, but I am not convinced that “essence” is a helpful description of God’s unchanging core. Without a treatment of simplicity, significant questions are raised about what Peckham means by “essence” and how this relates to the divine attributes he treats.
In addition, he rejects several significant pillars of the classic account of the incarnation without acknowledging that he is doing so. At several places, he rejects what patristic scholars call “bipartite exegesis,” that is, the attribution of certain things Jesus does to his divine nature and others to his human nature. This was essential to maintaining the classic doctrine of God’s essence, which Peckham seems to endorse, and its relation to Christ’s true divinity. To reject bipartite exegesis (which I am not opposed to doing), one must do some serious metaphysical rethinking. The implications are more significant than Peckham’s treatment would suggest.

<b>Conclusion</b>

However, despite these reservations, Peckham’s commitment to Scripture is admirable. What he says in his method is indeed his practice; he repeatedly presents Scripture and wrestles with its interpretation, interacting with contemporary Evangelical interpretation more than many of his peers. Peckham is also clear in his presentation that theology ought to lead us to doxology. Despite significant points of disagreement, I am thankful for Peckham’s thoughtful engagement with Scripture and its teaching concerning our God. The reader has much to gain if they read Divine Attributes in interaction with Scripture, asking if there is indeed biblical warrant for the claims that Peckham makes.

Was this review helpful?